Summary of points based on questions by Marg.
Tarski wrote:I am not even sure that Godel himself used the term "God-like".
The argument is often formulated symbolically without the use of any common language nouns such as "God".
Q. Then why are we discussing the argument in word form?
Ans. It is considered easier to understand in that form as long as one doesn't not read anything more into the words than is given in the definition. JAK is doing that and assumes that the argument pivots on such connotations. It doesn't, at least not in the case of the property defined as
"
has as essential properties those and only those properties which are positive". We use "God-like" as a name for that defined property.
Q. Isn't it true that existence is not a property?
Ans. This is the usual criticism of ontological arguments and it is a good one. Why is JAK not satisfied to take that approach?
Godel's argument seems to have a similar problem with "necessary existence".
JAK keeps acting like I am defending the whole argument and its application to theology.
I am not. I only want him to focus on what the real problems are. He says that definition 1 assumes God's existence if I understand him correctly (but it doesn't). That would be begging the question if it did (see the definition I quoted). But then he turns around and say he never said that definition one begs the question. huh? Sounds as if he is confused. If it assumes God's existence then it begs the question of God's existence which is what is supposed to be proved (in Godel's specific sense).
Q. Why should we be convinced that symbols can translate exactly into words with concepts?
Ans. Good question. Indeed "positive" seems unlikely to be an exact match for something real. But also the symbols in a symbolic deductive argument may apply to totally different real situations. The very same symbolic argument might possibly be mapped onto more than one situation which can be described in English. This is one big point about the first order predicate calculus. For example, there is more than one model for axiomatic hyperbolic geometry.
But Godel wants to make a connection with familiar concepts via the notion of "positive" property. He is where one of the main problems lies. Why should we accept that there actually is such a property?
On the other had, God-like is not but a word that he defines in terms "positive property". He is not assuming God-like, he is merely defining it as a word to use to mean what is captured in the long phrase above. For the argument to apply to something real, we must assume that there is a real notion of positive that satisfies his intuitive axioms.
Q. Isn't it true that not all modal logicians accept Godel's argument in word form as being sound. [/quote]
Ans. Right! They don't and neither do I. I am guessing that most don't. But some do consider it to be at least a
valid argument (note the distinction).
The analysis in the prestigious Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy gives the following analysis which is at total variance with JAK's claims about defintion 1 and the issue of inappropriately assuming the existence of what is to be shown to exist.
Q. So what is wrong with the argument? Perhaps it's not so much that a God is assumed but rather Godel's god is..even if Godel's god is simply what can be conceived.
Ans. It seems to me that there are at least two things that need to be assumed for the formal argument to be sound as applied to the actual world. One is that there is a real life workable notion of "positive". This is problematic for sure but it is far more intuitive and accessible than the concept of God. This is why Godel's proof would have some value to anyone who already accepted that such a notion of
positive had reality. Second, and related to the first, we seem to need to be committed to some sort of Platonism. His notion of positivity has to be so objective that we probably need the platonic world for it to reside in. But then the platonic world is far from established and seems not to be admissible to empirical analysis.
Q. So what exactly are the properties of Godel's god?
Ans. So far as what he hopes to prove here, Godel's God would be a being that
has as essential properties those and only those properties which are positive. He would have shown no more than that if the proof had worked.
But Godel's personal notion of God seems like a sophisticated version of Plato's "The Good". It is entirely unphysical and has the same sort of existence as Plato thought that numbers had.
Not the kind of God that Christians and Muslims seem to accept.
Q. Well what God does the argument prove, what properties does this God have?
Ans. Only the property described by the bolded phrase above and anything else that follows deductive from it. Nothing more.
Not much use to a Christian or Muslim is it?
Given a sufficiently generous conception of properties, and granted the acceptability of the underlying modal logic, the listed theorems do follow from the axioms. (This point was argued in detail by Dana Scott, in lecture notes which circulated for many years and which were transcribed in Sobel 1987 and published in Sobel 2004. It is also made by Sobel, Anderson, and Adams.) So, criticisms of the argument are bound to focus on the axioms, or on the other assumptions which are required in order to construct the proof.
Q, what about the fact that a certain professor says there isn't consensus even among modal logicians with Peter Geach being one who doesn't accept as sound ontological arguments for God?
Ans. Neither do I accept it as sound! Neither does the SEP. They just identify the problems correctly. JAK does not. (Unless somehow I have confused what Marg said with what JAK said)
I claim that definition 1 does not assume the existence of God and that it is a definition and no a claim. I also claim that Godel's arguments does not impropery depend on connotations of the word "god" found in his coinage "God-like" (the latter being only short hand for the property described by the bolded phrase above).
Nothing more. If JAK now agrees with me then fine--but I thought that's what he meant when he said that definition1 "assumed".
JAK also said that definition 1 was a
claim. But it isn't.
In logic and mathematics, a phrase such as
Definition. An X is an A that has property B (notice that the label "Definition plays a role here).
means
We definite the word X to be a descriptive word that refers to, by definition, anything that is an A and also has property B.
See! Its not a claim. This is a simple and ubiquitous convention that JAK seems unaware of.
Example:
Definition: A prime is a positive integer that is divisible only by 1 and itself.
That's not a claim, its a definition just as is Godel's definition of property G (God-like). Notice that
prime had several common meanings and connotations before this definition was made but these don't enter into any number theory argument.
Q. Isn't there is something intuitively wrong with any argument for a God concept, which claims to provide some sort of reliable conclusion.
Ans. I feel the same way, especially if what is meant by the word God is anything like what most people imagine. To demonstrate such a God, we would need
empirical evidence and plenty of it (it's and extraordinary claim).
Godel tries to circumvent this by implicit use of a platonic ontology but in the end it isn't convincing.
postscript:
As for why JAK gets attacked, it could have something to do with the fact that he writes long tedious hit and miss analyses that are full of misguided accusations of fallacies and other things that show he is sort of cutting and pasting ideas often just beyond his grasp. For one example, how does one not see that defintion1 is a definition, not a claim?? It's infuriating (but made my professor friend laugh out loud).
Even if the identification of fallacies is done correctly (a big if in JAK's case), the overuse of fallacy accusations is also stylistically poor.
I agree with what Gad wrote once:
http://gadianton2.tripod.com/index.blog?from=20060115
when believers want to give their claims more weight, they dress these claims up in scientific terms. When believers want to belittle atheism or secular humanism, they call it a "religion". -Beastie
yesterday's Mormon doctrine is today's Mormon folklore.-Buffalo